What is Immanuel Kant’s Transcendental Idealism?

cover

Transcendental idealism is foundational to many of German philosopher Immanuel Kant’s (1724-1804) ideas.

It emphasizes a distinction between what subjects (human beings) can experience (the natural, observable world) and what subjects cannot (“supersensible” objects such as God and the soul). In its most simple form, it says that subjects have cognition of appearances but not of things in themselves (1). By “thing in itself,” Kant meant a thing standing outside any relation to our cognitive powers, but still a thing that one receives a representation of.

Commentators have interpreted Kant’s doctrine in various ways. One such interpretation is in the way of radical skepticism in that Kant seemed to reduce all objects of human knowledge to representations in the human mind. This would seem to deny that humans have the capacity to know anything genuine about reality. Other interpreters believe that Kant did not deny the existence of objects external to the human mind; in fact, they suggest that Kant’s doctrine assumes that real things must exist externally to the mind so that the human mind can receive representations of these things.

A causal interpretation of Kant’s doctrine is based on the idea that he often distinguished appearances from things in themselves (2). Kant stated that “Objects in themselves are not known to us at all, and what we call external objects are nothing but representations of our sensibility, whose form is space, but whose true correlate, i.e. the thing in itself, is not and cannot be recognized through them” (3). On the causality view, things existing in themselves are distinct from their appearances. Appearances are the subjective mental states the things cause within the human mind. There is, on this view, a causal relationship between things in themselves and appearances. Appearances are subjective states within the human mind that are caused by things in themselves outside of the human mind. Sometimes this view is referred to as the “two worlds” interpretation because it posits that appearances and things in themselves constitute two different worlds, or two separate realms of distinct entities.

The other interpretation of Kant’s doctrine is the identity interpretation (4). Here there isn’t a distinguishing between two separate entities (appearances and things in themselves), but rather between the same entity as it appears (considered in relation to our cognitive faculties) and as it exists in itself (considered apart from that relation). The basic premise is that every appearance is identical to a thing in itself and the distinction is not between two different entities but two ways to thinking about or referring to the same entity. Thus, appearances are not merely subjective entities or states of our minds because they have an existence in themselves.

Both interpretations agree that real things exist, that these things cause representations in us, that objects are given to us through the senses, and that sensing and thinking are subject to conditions that make synthetic a priori cognition possible.

References

1. Wood, A. 2004. Kant. p. 63.

2. Wood, A. 2004. Ibid. p. 64.

3. Kant, I. 1781. Critique of Pure Reason. Section 1: Transcendental Doctrine of Elements

4. Wood, A. 2004. Ibid. p. 65.

Advertisement

7 comments

Let me know your thoughts!

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s